Skip to main content
Advertisement
Browse Subject Areas
?

Click through the PLOS taxonomy to find articles in your field.

For more information about PLOS Subject Areas, click here.

  • Loading metrics

What Happens after Inbreeding Avoidance? Inbreeding by Rejected Relatives and the Inclusive Fitness Benefit of Inbreeding Avoidance

  • A. Bradley Duthie ,

    aduthie@abdn.ac.uk

    Affiliation Institute of Biological and Environmental Sciences, School of Biological Sciences, University of Aberdeen, Aberdeen, United Kingdom

  • Jane M. Reid

    Affiliation Institute of Biological and Environmental Sciences, School of Biological Sciences, University of Aberdeen, Aberdeen, United Kingdom

Abstract

Avoiding inbreeding, and therefore avoiding inbreeding depression in offspring fitness, is widely assumed to be adaptive in systems with biparental reproduction. However, inbreeding can also confer an inclusive fitness benefit stemming from increased relatedness between parents and inbred offspring. Whether or not inbreeding or avoiding inbreeding is adaptive therefore depends on a balance between inbreeding depression and increased parent-offspring relatedness. Existing models of biparental inbreeding predict threshold values of inbreeding depression above which males and females should avoid inbreeding, and predict sexual conflict over inbreeding because these thresholds diverge. However, these models implicitly assume that if a focal individual avoids inbreeding, then both it and its rejected relative will subsequently outbreed. We show that relaxing this assumption of reciprocal outbreeding, and the assumption that focal individuals are themselves outbred, can substantially alter the predicted thresholds for inbreeding avoidance for focal males. Specifically, the magnitude of inbreeding depression below which inbreeding increases a focal male’s inclusive fitness increases with increasing depression in the offspring of a focal female and her alternative mate, and it decreases with increasing relatedness between a focal male and a focal female’s alternative mate, thereby altering the predicted zone of sexual conflict. Furthermore, a focal male’s inclusive fitness gain from avoiding inbreeding is reduced by indirect opportunity costs if his rejected relative breeds with another relative of his. By demonstrating that variation in relatedness and inbreeding can affect intra- and inter-sexual conflict over inbreeding, our models lead to novel predictions for family dynamics. Specifically, parent-offspring conflict over inbreeding might depend on the alternative mates of rejected relatives, and male-male competition over inbreeding might lead to mixed inbreeding strategies. Making testable quantitative predictions regarding inbreeding strategies occurring in nature will therefore require new models that explicitly capture variation in relatedness and inbreeding among interacting population members.

Introduction

Inbreeding, defined as mating between related individuals, is a pervasive force in evolutionary ecology that is postulated to drive the evolution of mating systems [13] and dispersal [4, 5], and to influence population dynamics [6, 7] and the expression and persistence of mutation load [8, 9]. Understanding these phenomena therefore requires a thorough understanding of the evolution and occurrence of inbreeding itself.

Reproducing individuals might exhibit strategies of inbreeding preference or avoidance defined as mating with more or less closely related individuals than expected given random mating, or exhibit inbreeding tolerance defined as random mating with respect to relatedness [10]. In general, the evolution of any such inbreeding strategy is expected to depend on the balance between increased inheritance of identical-by-descent alleles by inbred offspring versus any decrease in survival or reproductive fitness of those inbred offspring due to inbreeding depression. This balance is well understood in the context of the evolution of self-fertilisation versus outcrossing [1116]. Specifically, in an outcrossing population, a mutant allele causing self-fertilisation (the most extreme degree of inbreeding) is 50% more likely to be inherited identical-by-descent by the selfing individual’s offspring than a homologous wild type allele underlying outcrossing, but resulting inbred offspring will commonly show inbreeding depression [2, 12, 13, 17]. The net inclusive fitness benefit of self-fertilisation, and hence the frequency of the underlying mutant allele, will therefore depend on the balance between increased offspring inheritance of identical-by-descent alleles versus reduced offspring survival or reproductive fitness [12, 13, 1518].

The net inclusive fitness benefit of biparental inbreeding (i.e., inbreeding between two non-self individuals) depends on this same balance. Inbreeding depression is widespread and can substantially reduce offspring fitness in populations with biparental fertilisation [7, 19, 20]. Consequently, inbreeding depression is widely presumed to drive the evolution of inbreeding avoidance in such populations [12, 2123]. But the inclusive fitness increment of biparental inbreeding relative to outbreeding—which stems from the higher probability that identical-by-descent alleles will be inherited by inbred offspring—has been less widely factored into verbal or quantitative models regarding the evolution of biparental inbreeding versus inbreeding avoidance [10].

Models examining the evolution of self-fertilisation cannot be directly extrapolated to predict the evolution of biparental inbreeding strategy because they do not account for sex-specific inclusive fitness benefits or differing reproductive strategies between males and females with potentially conflicting evolutionary interests [10]. Instead, Parker [24, 25] provided a basic conceptual model that specifically emphasised the inclusive fitness benefit of biparental inbreeding stemming from increased probability of identity-by-descent, and this model was subsequently extended by Waser et al. [26], Kokko and Ots [27], and Puurtinen [28]. These models emphasise that inbreeding preference or tolerance might be adaptive even when inbreeding depression occurs. They also predict evolutionary sexual conflict over inbreeding, meaning that selection on inbreeding preference, tolerance, or avoidance might differ between males and females [24, 25]. This sexual conflict arises because reproductive investment in inbred offspring differentially affects the mean inclusive fitness of each sex (assuming different sex roles). If an individual of the sex whose reproduction is limited by resource availability inbreeds, resources will be invested in less fit inbred offspring instead of fitter outbred offspring. In contrast, an individual of the sex whose reproduction is limited by mate availability might be able to inbreed without losing outbreeding success, as in systems where the mate-limited sex provides no parental care. Where some care is provided, the relative cost of inbreeding for the mate-limited sex has been modelled and interpreted as an opportunity cost in terms of missed opportunities to outbreed [24, 25]. Because some asymmetric investment in offspring is the norm in systems with biparental reproduction, sexual conflict is predicted to be a fundamental outcome of biparental inbreeding.

However, existing models of biparental inbreeding make strong and restrictive assumptions. Most assume that the focal population primarily comprises outbred and unrelated individuals, but also contains two focal relatives that might or might not inbreed with each other [2426]. Under these assumptions, if a focal individual avoids inbreeding, then its rejected relative must also avoid inbreeding. These models therefore implicitly assume mutual inbreeding avoidance. In contrast, Puurtinen [28] assumes that females can optimise their inbreeding by selecting males that are related to a specific degree. These conditions are very unlikely to apply in wild populations in which biparental inbreeding might occur. Rather, both non-relatives and relatives of different (but unlikely all optimal) degrees are likely to be available as potential mates. Consequently, relatives that are rejected as mates by a focal individual might subsequently inbreed to varying degrees whether by choice or coercion, or might avoid inbreeding. For example, inbreeding might benefit rejected relatives if the encounter rate between potential mates is low, meaning that avoiding subsequent inbreeding would increase the risk of breeding failure [27, 29]. Alternatively, rejected females might be subsequently coerced into mating with another relative [24, 25, 30]. Therefore, a focal individual that is ‘deciding’ whether or not to inbreed cannot necessarily ensure or assume that its rejected relative will subsequently outbreed.

The degree to which rejected relatives subsequently inbreed is likely to be critical to inclusive fitness calculations. Conceptual models that assume reciprocal inbreeding avoidance [2426] or the availability of optimally related kin [28] would have limited applicability or predictive ability when the inclusive fitness benefits of inbreeding versus avoiding inbreeding are conditional upon the subsequent mating decisions of rejected relatives. Nevertheless, multiple studies have attempted to apply quantitative predictions derived from existing models of biparental inbreeding [2427] to empirical systems [3134]. Here we show that these predictions are unlikely to be accurate when highly restrictive assumptions are violated.

We first formally summarise and review Parker’s [24, 25] basic conceptual model (hereafter ‘Parker’s model’) that illustrates the balance between the inclusive fitness benefit of biparental inbreeding and inbreeding depression. We then extend this model in three ways. First, we relax the assumption that focal individuals are outbred. Second, we relax the assumption that the rejected relatives of focal individuals will subsequently outbreed. Finally, we demonstrate that indirect opportunity costs may exist if a focal male’s rejected potential mate subsequently breeds with his male relative. We discuss how our model relates to empirical and theoretical research on biparental inbreeding, and to the broader context of inclusive fitness theory. We thereby highlight new avenues of research for biparental inbreeding theory, including understanding family dynamics and ultimately a more predictive evolutionary theory of inbreeding strategy.

Parker’s model

Parker’s model evaluates the (inclusive) fitness costs and benefits of the decision to inbreed or avoid inbreeding for each sex. For convenience, the sexes whose reproduction is limited by mate availability and resource availability are labelled as ‘male’ and ‘female’, respectively. In the most basic model, males can mate with any number of females during a reproductive bout to increase their reproductive success, but females can only mate with one male and produce n offspring, which is assumed constant for all females and reproductive bouts. Mates can be unrelated and produce outbred offspring, or be related by some degree and produce correspondingly inbred offspring.

Parker’s model considers a potentially inbreeding focal male (M1) and focal female (F1) that are related by some degree rM1,F1 (Fig 1A). All other potential mates of M1 and F1 are assumed to be unrelated to both M1 and F1. Following inbreeding avoidance by one focal individual (M1 or F1), the other focal individual is therefore assumed to outbreed [2426]. For example, if M1 avoids inbreeding with F1, then F1 is assumed to outbreed with an alternative male M2 (Fig 1A). The most basic model assumes that M1’s opportunity to outbreed with unrelated females (e.g., F2 in Fig 1A), is unaffected by whether or not he inbreeds or avoids inbreeding with F1, so additional offspring that M1 might sire do not need to be included in inclusive fitness calculations. In contrast, if F1 inbreeds with M1, she cannot also outbreed.

thumbnail
Fig 1. Conceptual models of biparental inbreeding.

Females (F1 and F2) produce n offspring. The focal male (M1) is related by rM1,F1 to the focal female (F1). The fitness of M1 and F1’s n offspring is decreased by inbreeding depression δM1,F1. Whether or not M1 inbreeds or avoids inbreeding with F1 does not affect his opportunity to outbreed with an unrelated female (F2). In Parker’s [24, 25] model (A), if M1 avoids inbreeding, then F1 is assumed to outbreed with unrelated male (M2). In our extended model (B), if M1 avoids inbreeding, F1’s alternative mate M2 may be related to M1 (rM1,M2) or F1 (rM2,F1). If rM2,F1 > 0, then the fitness of M2 and F1’s offspring will be decreased by inbreeding depression (δM2,F1).

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0125140.g001

Parker [24, 25] calculated the inclusive fitness consequences of inbreeding versus avoiding inbreeding for M1 and F1. When M1 avoids inbreeding with F1, a proportion rM1,F1 of F1’s direct allelic contribution to her offspring will be identical-by-descent with alleles carried by M1. M1’s inclusive fitness increment from avoiding inbreeding is therefore n2×rM1,F1. Alternatively, if M1 inbreeds with F1, identical-by-descent alleles will be contributed to inbred offspring by both M1 (n2) and F1 (n2×rM1,F1). This increases M1’s inclusive fitness increment to n2+n2×rM1,F1. But this inclusive fitness increment due to inbreeding is decreased by inbreeding depression such that inbred offspring produced by M1 and F1 have (1 − δM1,F1) the fitness of outbred offspring [2427]. The magnitude of inbreeding depression below which inbreeding benefits M1 is given by the values of δM1,F1 for which the inclusive fitness gain from inbreeding exceeds that of avoiding inbreeding [2426], (1) Fig 2 shows threshold values of δM1,F1 below which inbreeding increases M1’s inclusive fitness given different values of rM1,F1. For the widely cited illustrative example where rM1,F1=12 (e.g., M1 and F1 are full siblings with unrelated parents), M1’s inclusive fitness from inbreeding exceeds that from avoiding inbreeding if δM1,F1<23 [10, 2427].

thumbnail
Fig 2. Zones of parameter space in which inbreeding versus avoiding inbreeding is predicted to increase male and female inclusive fitness when all other potential mates are unrelated.

The x-axis shows the relatedness (rM1,F1) between two focal potential mates, male M1 and female F1, where rM1,F1 = 0 equates to outbreeding, and rM1,F1 = 1 equates to self-fertilisation. The y-axis shows the magnitude of inbreeding depression (δM1,F1) below which inbreeding is beneficial for each sex. Areas where neither sex, both sexes, and males only benefit from inbreeding are shown in white, grey, and black, respectively. The intersections between black and white areas and black and grey areas respectively demarcate the thresholds below which M1 and F1 benefit by inbreeding [24, 25].

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0125140.g002

From the perspective of F1, the inclusive fitness gain from inbreeding with M1 versus avoiding inbreeding can be calculated similarly [24, 25]. Because M1’s additional outbreeding success is assumed to be unaffected by inbreeding with F1, it is irrelevant for calculating F1’s inclusive fitness. If F1 avoids inbreeding with M1 and outbreeds with M2 instead, her inclusive fitness is n2 (Fig 1A). If F1 inbreeds with M1, her inclusive fitness is n2(1+rM1,F1)(1δM1,F1). Inbreeding with M1 is therefore beneficial for F1 if, (2) Fig 2 shows that the threshold of inbreeding depression below which inbreeding benefits F1 is symmetrical to that for M1. For example, when F1 and M1 are full siblings, inbreeding benefits F1 if δM1,F1<13, compared to 23 for M1 [10, 2427].

Parker’s model could therefore be interpreted to predict that inbreeding tolerance or preference can be adaptive for one or both sexes, even given non-zero inbreeding depression (δM1,F1 > 0; Fig 2). It also predicts a zone of sexual conflict, where inbreeding increases male fitness but decreases female fitness for a substantial range of δM1,F1 (black zone, Fig 2). This zone is greatest given small rM1,F1 values and decreases to zero as rM1,F1 approaches 1 (self-fertilisation).

Relaxing the assumption that focal individuals are outbred

Parker’s model highlights that rM1,F1 is a key parameter underlying inclusive fitness calculations for inbreeding versus avoiding inbreeding, but rM1,F1 is rarely explicitly defined in biparental inbreeding theory (but see [10]). Parker’s [24] original derivation does not include rM1,F1 at all, and focuses only on the specific case in which potential mates share exactly half their alleles (e.g., outbred full siblings). Waser et al. [26] explicitly equated rM1,F1 to Wright’s [35] coefficient of relationship, while Parker [25] and Kokko and Ots [27] define rM1,F1 as ‘relatedness’ without further elaboration. Clearly, in order to calculate appropriate thresholds for inbreeding avoidance or preference (Ineqs. 1 and 2), relatedness must be appropriately defined for inclusive fitness calculations.

In particular, it is not always appreciated that the relevant rM1,F1 values depend on the degree to which focal individuals are themselves inbred. The alternative implicit assumption, that all focal individuals are outbred, is unlikely to be valid in populations where biparental inbreeding might occur. The inclusive fitness consequences of inbreeding versus avoiding inbreeding therefore need to be considered for focal individuals that are themselves inbred to some degree, by defining rM1,F1 appropriately. In their developments of Parker’s model, Lehmann and Perrin [36] and Puurtinen [28] account for inbred focal individuals by defining rM1,F1 as the regression coefficient of relatedness [37, 38]. But, to our knowledge, this definition has not been explicitly applied to Parker’s basic model.

If focal individuals are themselves inbred, then two homologous alleles have a non-zero probability of occurring identical-by-descent within an individual. Specifically, the probability that two of M1’s homologous alleles are identical-by-descent defines his coefficient of inbreeding fM1. The probability that an allele is directly transmitted to M1’s offspring then increases from 12 to 12(1+fM1). The regression coefficient of relatedness (henceforth denoted rM1,F1) is the proportion of M1’s alleles expected to be carried identical-by-descent by F1 [38]. Therefore, M1’s relatedness to F1 is, (3) The coefficient of kinship fM1,F1 (sometimes denoted as kM1,F1 or θ M1,F1) is the probability that an allele randomly sampled from M1 is identical-by-descent with a homologous allele randomly sampled from F1, and is therefore symmetrical between two individuals (i.e., fM1,F1 = fF1,M1). But if two individuals M1 and F1 are inbred to different degrees (fM1fF1), their relatedness—calculated in the context of inclusive fitness [37]—may be asymmetrical (rM1,F1rF1,M1), so that F1’s relatedness to M1 is, (4) This asymmetry occurs because the denominators of Eqs (3) and (4) contain M1 and F1’s coefficients of inbreeding, respectively, which will differ if M1 and F1 are inbred to different degrees.

We now reformulate Parker’s model using Eqs (3) and (4) to show how fM1,F1, fM1, and fF1 affect the predicted thresholds for inbreeding avoidance versus tolerance or preference. Substituting Eq (3) into Ineq. (1) for M1 yields the inbreeding depression threshold below which M1 benefits by inbreeding with F1, (5) Substituting Eq (4) into Ineq. (2) gives the inbreeding depression threshold below which F1 benefits by inbreeding with M1, (6) These expressions show that the thresholds for inbreeding versus inbreeding avoidance depend directly on the coefficient of inbreeding of each focal individual, but do not depend on that of their potential mate. Increasing fM1 increases the right hand side of Ineq. (5), whereas increasing fF1 decreases the right hand side of Ineq. (6). Inbred males therefore benefit by inbreeding at higher thresholds of δM1,F1 than outbred males, and inbred females benefit by avoiding inbreeding at higher δM1,F1 thresholds than outbred females. Our extension of Parker’s model therefore shows that the degree to which focal individuals are inbred cannot be ignored when calculating relatedness, and hence when inferring thresholds defining sex-specific inbreeding strategy.

Relaxing the assumption of mutual inbreeding avoidance

While Parker’s model illustrates that inbreeding can be adaptive and that sexual conflict over inbreeding might occur, any quantitative conclusions are limited by the strong assumption that rejected relatives will not inbreed. We now extend Parker’s model to show that subsequent inbreeding by a rejected relative can greatly alter the inclusive fitness benefit of avoiding inbreeding for a focal male, and therefore alter the benefit of inbreeding versus inbreeding avoidance and change the expected magnitude of sexual conflict over inbreeding.

To relax the assumption that the focal M1’s rejected relative F1 will outbreed, we allow F1’s alternative mate M2 to be related to M1, F1, or both by rM1,M2 and rF1,M2, respectively (Fig 1B). We limit our model to one additional relative (M2), rather than many differently related individuals for tractability. Our current aim is simply to demonstrate that an additional relative can affect inbreeding depression thresholds defining inbreeding strategies, not to predict evolutionary outcomes that might arise given realistic relatedness distributions within populations; we therefore do not assume that a focal population comprises only three relatives, or that this situation will persist over evolutionary time (see Discussion).

If F1 breeds with M2 after M1 avoids inbreeding with her, then inbreeding with F1 is beneficial for M1 if, (7) In Ineq. (7), δM2,F1 is the inbreeding depression in offspring produced by M2 and F1. The right hand side of Ineq. (7) reduces to that of Ineq. (1) when M2 is unrelated to M1 and F1 (i.e., rM1,M2 = 0 and δM2,F1 = 0). The inclusive fitness gain M1 receives by inbreeding with F1 remains the same as in Parker’s model (left hand side of Ineqs. 1 and 7) because rM1,F1 and δM1,F1 are unchanged (Fig 1A and 1B). Inequality (Eq 7) shows that M1’s fitness gain from avoiding inbreeding with F1 changes if F1 subsequently breeds with a related M2 (whether by choice or coercion). This is because rM1,M2 or δM2,F1, or both, will be non-zero and hence affect M1’s inclusive fitness. Although F1 will pass alleles to her offspring produced with M2 that are identical-by-descent to alleles carried by M1, the indirect fitness benefit to M1 will be decreased by any inbreeding depression in F1’s offspring that occurs when F1 inbreeds with a related M2. But if M1 avoids inbreeding with F1, he can potentially gain indirect fitness through F1’s alternative mate M2 if M1 and M2 are related (i.e., rM1,M2 > 0; Fig 1B). Explicitly considering non-zero relatedness among M1, F1, and M2 can therefore increase or decrease M1’s inclusive fitness gain from inbreeding versus avoiding inbreeding.

In contrast, alternative female mates of M1 (and M2) do not need to be considered when determining whether F1’s inclusive fitness is increased by inbreeding with M1 versus M2 if the outbreeding success of both males is unaffected by F1’s decision. The conditions where inbreeding with M1 increases F1’s inclusive fitness more than breeding with M2 can be found by comparing F1’s relatedness to each male and the inbreeding depression in the resulting offspring. Inbreeding with M1 instead of M2 increases the inclusive fitness of F1 if, (8) The left hand side of Ineq. (8) is identical to that of Ineq. (2), and the right hand side reduces to that of Ineq. (2) when rF1,M2 = 0 and δM2,F1 = 0.

To illustrate the inclusive fitness consequences that result from relaxing Parker’s [24, 25] assumption of reciprocal inbreeding avoidance, we first consider three specific scenarios. We use these scenarios as examples to illustrate why the existence of additional related potential mates is important for predicting the evolution of inbreeding strategy, not to make specific quantitative predictions for any particular species. Furthermore, the three focal individuals considered in each scenario are not assumed to be the only individuals within a focal population, nor are their relatedness combinations assumed to be representative of the full relatedness structure of a larger population. Our objective here is simply to show that the presence of a related potential mate affects inclusive fitness calculations. Scenario 1 illustrates a case in which all three focal individuals are equally related. Scenario 2 introduces an example in which relatedness differs among all three focal individuals. Scenario 3 illustrates that when F1 is related to M1 and M2, both δM1,F1 and δM2,F1 affect inbreeding depression thresholds. Following the three illustrative scenarios, we define inbreeding depression as a function of kinship to facilitate comparison with Parker’s model, and provide a systematic summary of the implications of Ineqs. (7) and (8). For simplicity, our illustrative scenarios assume that focal individuals are outbred, but this is not a condition of Ineqs. (7) and (8) given that relatedness is appropriately defined.

Scenario 1: M1, F1, and M2 are all equally related

If M1, F1, and M2 are all equally related (Fig 3A and 3B), then the magnitude of inbreeding depression in F1’s offspring can be assumed to be the same whether she mates with M1 or M2 (δM1,F1 = δM2,F1). Solving Ineq. (7) given these conditions reveals that inbreeding with F1 increases M1’s inclusive fitness more than avoiding inbreeding with F1 if δM1,F1 < 1. Therefore, assuming there are no additional costs of inbreeding, M1 will never benefit from avoiding inbreeding if F1 subsequently inbreeds with an equally close relative of both M1 and F1. This conclusion contrasts with Parker’s model that assumes M2 is unrelated to M1 and F1 (Fig 1A), and which predicts that M1’s inclusive fitness is increased by avoiding inbreeding given sufficiently high δM1,F1 (Fig 2).

thumbnail
Fig 3. Three illustrative scenarios of biparental inbreeding in which the inclusive fitness benefits to a focal male M1 and female F1 depend on their relatedness to the female’s alternative mate M2.

F1 produces n offspring, whose fitness is reduced by inbreeding depression δM1,F1 or δM2,F1 if she mates with M1 or M2, respectively. In scenario 1 (A and B), M1, F1, and M2 are all equally related such that rM1,F1 = rM1,M2 = rM2,F1 = r. In scenario 2 (C and D), M1 and F1 are half-siblings, M1 and M2 are first cousins, and M2 and F1 are unrelated. In scenario 3 (E and F), M1 and F1 are half-siblings, M1 and F1 are first cousins, and M1 and M2 are unrelated.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0125140.g003

From F1’s point of view, there is no fitness difference between inbreeding with M1 versus M2 because rF1,M1 = rF1,M2 and hence δM1,F1 = δM2,F1 (Ineq. 8; Fig 1A and 1B). If an unrelated M3 is also available, then the threshold of inbreeding depression below which inbreeding with M1 or M2 is beneficial for F1 does not change from Parker’s model (Ineq. 2; Fig 2).

Scenario 2: M1 and F1 are half-siblings; M1 and M2 are cousins

In the scenario illustrated in Fig 3C and 3D, M1 and F1 are outbred half-siblings (rM1,F1=14), M1 and M2 are outbred first cousins (rM1,M2=18), and M2 and F1 are unrelated (rM2,F1 = 0). Because M2 and F1 are unrelated, there is no inbreeding depression in M2 and F1’s offspring (δM2,F1 = 0). Solving Ineq. (7) for δM1,F1 shows that M1 increases his inclusive fitness more by inbreeding with F1 rather than avoiding inbreeding with her if δM1,F1<710. This threshold is lower than that predicted by Parker’s model (δM1,F1<45), which assumes that M2 is unrelated to M1 and F1 (Fig 2). The two thresholds differ because rM1,M2 > 0. This scenario illustrates that when M1 and M2 are related, but F1 and M2 are not, the threshold value of inbreeding depression below which inbreeding with F1 benefits M1 is lower than predicted by Parker’s model. In contrast, because F1 and M2 are unrelated, F1 increases her inclusive fitness by inbreeding with M1 at the same values of δM1,F1 as predicted by Parker’s model (Fig 1A; Ineq. 2), namely δM1,F1<15. The combined decrease in M1’s inbreeding depression threshold and lack of change in F1’s threshold decreases the zone of δM1,F1 values over which sexual conflict exists compared to Parker’s model.

Scenario 3: M1 and F1 are half siblings: M2 and F1 are cousins

In a final illustrative scenario, M1 and F1 are outbred half-siblings, and M2 is an outbred cousin of F1 and unrelated to M1, such that rM1,F1=14, rM1,M2 = 0, and rF1,M2=18 (Fig 3E and 3F). Here F1’s offspring will be inbred whether she mates with M1 or M2. Therefore, it is likely that δM1,F1 > 0 and δM2,F1 > 0, so both will affect the conditions under which M1 increases his inclusive fitness by inbreeding versus avoiding inbreeding with F1 (Fig 3E and 3F). From Ineq. (7), M1 increases his inclusive fitness by inbreeding with F1 if 4 > 5δM1,F1δM2,F1. In contrast, F1 will benefit by inbreeding with her half-brother M1 rather than her cousin M2 if 1 > 10δM1,F1 − 9δM2,F1 (Ineq. 8). Any general solution to these inequalities requires a comparison of δM1,F1 and δM2,F1, which requires a function relating parental kinship to the magnitude of inbreeding depression in offspring. We now provide such a function, and thereby provide a systematic analysis of Ineqs. (7) and (8).

Systematic analysis of inbreeding avoidance thresholds

To better illustrate inbreeding depression thresholds and facilitate comparison with Parker’s model for M1 and F1 when M2 may be related to either or both, we define inbreeding depression as a function of M1 and F1’s coefficient of kinship fM1,F1, which is equal to their offsprings’ coefficient of inbreeding (foff). From first principles, offspring fitness (Woff) is expected to decrease as a log-linear function of foff such that ln(Woff) = −β0β1 foff, assuming that genetic and environmental influences on fitness are independent and that genetic effects are multiplicative across loci [7, 39, 40]. The slope β1 measures the load expressed due to inbreeding, and the intercept β0 can be interpreted as a measure of load that is independent of inbreeding, but potentially includes environmental and genetic effects expressed in an outbred population [41]. The fitness of offspring produced by M1 and F1 can therefore be defined as, (9) By substituting Eq (9) into Ineq. (7) and solving for β1, the conditions under which M1 increases his inclusive fitness by inbreeding versus avoiding inbreeding with F1 can be derived in terms of coefficients of kinship and inbreeding instead of δM1,F1 and δM2,F1, (10) The analogous condition under which a focal female F1 increases her inclusive fitness by inbreeding versus avoiding inbreeding with M1 is given by substituting Eq (9) into Ineq. (8), (11) Inequalities Eqs (10) and (11) define threshold inbreeding depression slopes below which inbreeding is beneficial for M1 and F1, respectively, given that F1’s alternative mate M2 might be related to M1, F1, or both. These inequalities can be used to compare threshold values that previously could only be expressed in terms of both δM1,F1 and δM2,F1. For example, given scenario 3 (Fig 3E and 3F), inbreeding with F1 increases M1’s inclusive fitness more than avoiding inbreeding with her if β1M1<25.75. By contrast, Parker’s model predicts β1M1<12.88 assuming fM1,F1=18, fM1,M2 = 0, and fM2,F1 = 0. From the perspective of F1, inbreeding with M1 increases F1’s inclusive fitness more than inbreeding with M2 if β1F1<1.69 given scenario 3, but Parker’s model predicts β1F1<1.79. Our example scenario 3 therefore illustrates that the presence of a related M2 can affect the threshold slopes below which inbreeding is beneficial for a focal M1 and F1, potentially increasing the predicted zone of sexual conflict over inbreeding.

Moving away from the three simple illustrative scenarios, a more systematic analysis of inbreeding depression thresholds can be obtained using Ineqs. (10) and (11) for different kinship and inbreeding coefficients among M1, F1, and M2. Fig 4 illustrates how β1M1 and β1F1 vary with fM1,F1, fM1,M2, and fM2,F1. For ease of illustration, these figures assume that focal individuals are outbred (fM1 = 0 and fF1 = 0), but Ineqs. (10) and (11) do not require these conditions. Each panel shows a single constant combination of fM2,F1 and fM1,M2 values. The top left panel is equivalent to the classic figure derived from Parker’s model (i.e., Fig 2) from rM1,F1 = 0 to rM1,F1 = 0.5 on the x-axis, but with sex-specific thresholds for inbreeding versus inbreeding avoidance and resulting sexual conflict expressed in terms of ln(β1) rather than δM1,F1. Fig 4 shows that fM2,F1 and fM1,M2 both affect the conditions under which inbreeding with F1 benefits M1 (Ineq. 10). Increases in fM2,F1 (columns from left to right) increase β1M1, while increases in fM1,M2 (rows from top to bottom) decrease β1M1. In contrast, increases in fM2,F1 (columns from left to right) decrease β1F1, but fM1,M2 does not affect β1F1 (Ineq. 11). Fig 4 also shows that the zone of sexual conflict over inbreeding between M1 and F1 (black zone) increases with increasing fM2,F1 (left to right) due to higher inbreeding depression in F1’s offspring when F1 mates with her relative M2 (which reduces M1’s inclusive fitness).

thumbnail
Fig 4. Zones of parameter space in which inbreeding versus inbreeding avoidance is predicted to increase male and female inclusive fitness given varying kinship between M1, F1, and M2.

Inbreeding depression thresholds (y-axis shown on a natural log scale) illustrate the values below which M1 and F1 have higher inclusive fitness by inbreeding instead of avoiding inbreeding. If M1 and F1 do not inbreed, F1 is assumed to breed with M2, who may or not be related to M1 or F1. The kinship between M1 and F1 (fM1,F1) increases along the x-axis of all plots. fM2,F1 and fM1,M2 increase through 0, 0.0625, and 0.125 across left to right columns and top to bottom rows, respectively. Areas where neither sex, both sexes, and males only benefit from inbreeding are shown in white, grey, and black, respectively. Negative threshold values are mathematically possible for some parameter combinations, but are biologically unrealistic because they require that offspring fitness increases monotonically with inbreeding. Where negative thresholds would be required, inbreeding is therefore assumed to never be beneficial. For simplicity, these examples assume focal individuals are outbred.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0125140.g004

Overall, Fig 4 shows that relaxing one highly restrictive assumption of Parker’s model, that fM2,F1 = 0 and fM1,M2 = 0, can alter male and female thresholds of inbreeding avoidance and hence the predicted zone of sexual conflict. Although Fig 4 assumes that focal individuals are outbred, inspection of Ineqs. (10) and (11) shows that increasing fM1 increases the threshold below which M1 benefits by inbreeding with F1, whereas increasing fF1 decreases the threshold below which F1 benefits by inbreeding with M1. These patterns remain similar when a linear (i.e., W = −β0β1 foff) rather than a log-linear relationship between parental kinship and offspring fitness is assumed (Supporting Information S1 File). The effects of coefficients of kinship and inbreeding on inbreeding depression thresholds are therefore likely to be robust to different functions relating inbreeding to offspring fitness.

Opportunity cost of male inbreeding

Thus far, Parker’s basic model and our extensions to consider inbred focal individuals and related alternative males assumed that males do not forgo any additional outbreeding opportunities by inbreeding. This assumption may be unrealistic; if M1 inbreeds with F1, his opportunity to mate with F2 might decrease (Fig 1A). Parker [24, 25] showed that M1’s inclusive fitness gain through siring F2’s offspring will then decrease by some fraction, c, such that the cost of inbreeding to M1 is nc2 (c can also be interpreted as approximately the ratio of male to female parental investment [24]). If c = 1, M1’s fitness from outbreeding is completely lost if he inbreeds with F1 because both sexes invest equally and exclusively to produce n offspring. This cost of inbreeding for M1 can be included in Parker’s model [2426] so that, (12) Although Parker [24, 25] assumed an outbred population, Ineq. (12) applies to inbred focal individuals if relatedness between M1 and F1 (rM1,F1) is defined as the regression coefficient of relatedness (Eqs 3 and 4). Inequality (Eq 12) shows that the magnitude of inbreeding depression below which inbreeding with F1 benefits M1 decreases as c increases from zero. For example, if rM1,F1=12, then inbreeding with F1 increases M1’s inclusive fitness more than avoiding inbreeding with her if δM1,F1<2(1c)3, or, if M1 is inbred, then δM1,F1<(1+fM1)(1c)(1+fM1+2fM1,F1). If c = 0, then the threshold is the familiar δM1,F1<23 [2426]. If c = 1, then M1 cannot increase his fitness by inbreeding with F1 [24, 26]. To our knowledge, it has not been noted that avoiding inbreeding with F1 can increase M1’s inclusive fitness more than inbreeding with her even if inbreeding with F1 increases M1’s likelihood of obtaining additional mating opportunities (i.e., c < 0). Mathematically, this occurs when δM1,F1>23. It arises because the inclusive fitness benefit that M1 receives from the outbred offspring of F1 outweighs not only the potential cost of inbreeding in terms of M1’s reduced ability to sire offspring, but also some amount of inclusive fitness gain that could potentially result from access to new mates through inbreeding with F1 (e.g., in a polygynous system).

Parker’s model that includes the opportunity cost c (Ineq. 12) again assumes reciprocal inbreeding avoidance by the two focal individuals M1 and F1. We again relax this assumption by introducing a relative M2 and determine the effect on M1’s inclusive fitness gain from inbreeding versus avoiding inbreeding with F1. Both M1 and M2 will then experience an opportunity cost c of breeding with F1; moreover, these costs are not independent if rM1,M2 > 0. Specifically, M1 will experience an indirect inclusive fitness cost of avoiding inbreeding with F1 if he is related to F1’s alternative mate M2 (i.e., rM1,M2 > 0). In this case, M1’s inclusive fitness will decrease because of his relative M2’s reduced opportunity to sire offspring with other females. The indirect cost to M1 equals the opportunity cost to M2 (nc2) multiplied by rM1,M2. Extending our model that includes M2 (Ineq. 7) to include direct and indirect male opportunity costs shows that M1 increases his inclusive fitness by inbreeding with F1 instead of avoiding inbreeding with her if, (13) To explore this model, we again consider the three simple illustrative scenarios shown in Fig 3. In scenario 1, where M1, F1, and M2 are all equally related (Fig 3A and 3B), inbreeding with F1 increases M1’s inclusive fitness more than avoiding inbreeding with her if δM1,F1 < 1 − c. Therefore, if there is no opportunity cost, M1 benefits by inbreeding with F1 when δM1,F1 < 1, as discussed previously. But if c = 1, M1 never benefits by inbreeding (consistent with Parker [24] and Waser et al. [26]). Including an opportunity cost in scenario 1 therefore decreases the inbreeding depression threshold below which M1 benefits by inbreeding with F1 versus inbreeding avoidance.

In scenario 2 where rM1,F1=14, rM1,M2=18, and rM2,F1 = 0 (Fig 3C and 3D), δM2,F1 = 0 because M2 and F1 are unrelated. Rearranging Ineq. (13) reveals that M1’s inclusive fitness gain from inbreeding with F1 is higher than that gained by avoiding inbreeding if δM1,F1<710(1c). Again, inbreeding is never beneficial for M1 if c = 1.

In scenario 3 where rM1,F1=14, rM1,M2 = 0, and rM2,F1=18 (Fig 3E and 3F), Ineq. (13) reveals that M1 increases his inclusive fitness more by inbreeding with F1 than by avoiding inbreeding with her if 4 > 5δM1,F1δM2,F1 + 4c. If c = 0, this condition is satisfied for M1 if δM1,F1<45 (assuming δM2,F1 ≥ 0). But when c > 0, the values of δM1,F1 for which it is satisfied become more restricted. If c = 1, M1’s inclusive fitness is never greater when inbreeding with F1 except given unrealistically high outbreeding depression (i.e., δM2,F1δM1,F1).

Discussion

The fitness costs associated with inbreeding, primarily inbreeding depression in resulting offspring, have caused a widespread assumption among animal ecologists that inbreeding avoidance must be adaptive [10, 21, 22]. Meanwhile, empirical studies have reported a lack of inbreeding avoidance [34, 4247], or even an apparent preference for inbreeding [4852], causing a mismatch between expectations and data [27]. This mismatch is partially resolved by basic conceptual models of biparental inbreeding that imply that the inclusive fitness benefit of inbreeding might cause inbreeding tolerance or preference to be adaptive even given inbreeding depression in offspring fitness, and that predict sexual conflict over inbreeding [2428].

Here we show that relaxing key restrictive assumptions, namely that focal individuals are themselves outbred, and that inbreeding avoidance is mutual, changes key quantitative and qualitative predictions of Parker’s model [24, 25]. Specifically, the zone of sexual conflict over inbreeding increased when a focal male’s inclusive fitness gain from avoiding inbreeding decreased because his rejected female relative subsequently inbred. Conversely, the zone of sexual conflict decreased when a focal male’s rejected female relative instead mated with a male that was related to the focal male but not to her, thereby increasing the focal male’s inclusive fitness through his female relative’s alternative mate choice. Consequently, the zone of sexual conflict, and thus the sexually antagonistic selection that drives coevolving mating traits [53], will depend on the distributions of inbreeding and relatedness among potential mates, and on how these potential mates interact to determine inbreeding versus inbreeding avoidance among relatives.

Puurtinen’s [28] model differs from models that assume reciprocal inbreeding avoidance [2426]. Puurtinen [28] highlights an interesting algebraic implication of Parker’s model by deriving the stable degree of inbreeding when females mate with optimal relatives. His model assumes that optimally related mates are always available, and that sexual conflict is resolved in favour of females, with negligible male opportunity cost and linear inbreeding depression. Following from Parker’s model, Puurtinen’s [28] development also assumes that inclusive fitness effects are not conditional upon the mating decisions of relatives, so predictions might not be quantitatively applicable if this assumption is violated.

When the inclusive fitness effects of an individual’s behaviour are conditional upon the behaviour of other individuals, the effects of social interactions are non-additive [54, 55]. In such cases, the combined inclusive fitness effects of pair-wise social interactions for focal individuals cannot simply be added up. In contexts other than biparental inbreeding, the complicating effect of non-additivity has long been recognised [56], and there is growing consensus that social interactions are likely to have non-additive effects on inclusive fitness [55]. In the context of biparental inbreeding, additive inclusive fitness effects are widely assumed [2428], but are unlikely to be biologically realistic. Our extensions of Parker’s model suggest that conceptual models that assume reciprocal inbreeding avoidance [2426] or ubiquitous availability of optimally related kin [28] will have limited predictive ability when the foundational assumption of additive inclusive fitness effects is violated. To develop a comprehensive theory of inbreeding, it is therefore necessary to move beyond pair-wise interactions between potential mates and consider inbreeding conflict in the broader context of populations characterised by complex and non-additive interactions among realistic distributions of relatives.

Non-additive inclusive fitness effects are likely prevalent in both plant and animal populations in which biparental inbreeding occurs. Most models that focus on plants consider the fitness costs and benefits of self-fertilisation versus outcrossing, but assume that non-selfing individuals inevitably outbreed with no opportunity to cross with a non-self relative (but see [57]; [1116]). As in animal populations, when biparental inbreeding and inbreeding depression occur in plants [5860], inbreeding conflict is expected, though very few studies have considered how such conflict might be resolved [61].

New directions for inbreeding theory

Our extension of Parker’s model of inbreeding between M1 and F1 to include another relative M2 changed inclusive fitness outcomes both quantitatively and qualitatively, suggesting that comprehensive new theory regarding the evolution of biparental inbreeding needs to be developed to make quantitative predictions about inbreeding strategies. Our extension was minimal; to keep the model tractable while making our conceptual point, we only allowed three individuals to be related (e.g., F2 was assumed to be unrelated to M1, F1, and M2; Fig 1). In natural populations, multiple potential mates of both sexes might be related to each other to different degrees. A more comprehensive theory of biparental inbreeding that incorporates realistic variation in relatedness arising from any mating system and potential feedbacks between relatedness and (inclusive) fitness is likely needed to make useful quantitative predictions. The complexity inherent in modelling multiple interacting individuals that are related to different degrees due to internally consistent ancestry means that further extensions to simple algebraic models will quickly become intractable. Below we show how our model of inbreeding among more than two relatives creates novel predictions regarding inbreeding conflict among nuclear family members, and outline key steps towards predictive evolutionary models of inbreeding strategies.

Family dynamics.

The dynamics of interactions among nuclear family members, including mating strategies, are of major interest in evolutionary and behavioural ecology [6265]. Relaxing the assumption of additive inclusive fitness effects may alter predictions regarding within-family sexual conflict over inbreeding. For example, Parker’s model predicts the thresholds of inbreeding depression below which mother-son inbreeding increases inclusive fitness more than inbreeding avoidance to be δM1,F1<13 and δM1,F1<23 for an outbred mother and son, respectively (Ineqs. 1,2), implying mother-son conflict over inbreeding. But if following inbreeding avoidance by her son, the mother mates with her son’s father (as is likely in many socially monogamous animal mating systems) rather than outbreeding with a mutually unrelated male, her son’s inclusive fitness will increase because of his relatedness to his father [66]. If the son’s mother and father are unrelated, they will produce outbred full siblings of the focal son. Inequality (Eq 7) shows that the son’s threshold for inbreeding will then be δM1,F1<13 instead of δM1,F1<23. The magnitude of inbreeding depression below which a son increases his inclusive fitness by inbreeding with his mother is therefore identical to that for his mother, eliminating mother-son conflict.

In contrast, father-daughter conflict over inbreeding is not predicted to be eliminated. This is because any alternative mate of a daughter that is related to her father must also be related to her. Therefore, daughters cannot outbreed with their father’s relatives in the same way that mothers can with their son’s relatives. Thus, while Waser et al. [26] suggest that mother-son inbreeding should be rarer than father-daughter inbreeding because sexual conflict is more likely to be resolved in favour of older individuals, such age effects need not be invoked if a son’s mother will likely continue to breed with his father. If a son has high confidence in the identity of both parents, he might benefit from ensuring that his parents continue to breed together to ensure the production of full siblings (i.e., “mother guarding”; [67]). If the alternative mate of a son’s mother is not his father, the son will be less closely related to his mother’s offspring, decreasing his inclusive fitness gain from avoiding inbreeding with his mother and therefore potentially leading to inbreeding conflict. This simple example illustrates that accounting for the alternative mates of relatives will be necessary for any comprehensive theory of family dynamics.

Male-male conflict over inbreeding with a mutual female relative.

While inter-sexual conflict over inbreeding is often emphasised, the evolution of inbreeding strategy might also be affected by interactions between same-sex relatives. Our model assumed that the inbreeding strategy of any one focal male was not directly affected by the strategies of other males. Specifically, we assumed that when a focal male M1 avoided inbreeding, the other male M2 mated with the focal female F1. We further assumed that when M1 inbred with F1, M2 did not interfere. But in reality, M1 and M2 might mutually compete to inbreed with F1, or might mutually avoid inbreeding. If inbreeding conflict is generally resolved in favour of females, meaning that females are successful at avoiding inbreeding when it benefits them to do so, then there might be little selection for males to attempt inbreeding when there is sexual conflict. Alternatively, if inbreeding conflict is generally resolved in favour of males, then a focal male’s reproductive success will be affected by both his own inbreeding or inbreeding avoidance strategies and the strategies of his male relatives. For example, competition between M1 and M2 may affect the inclusive fitness benefits of inbreeding. Details of the mating system are therefore likely to strongly influence the resolution of sexual conflict [25, 68].

As an illustrative example, if M1 and M2 are equally related to F1 and inbreeding depression is strong, then M1 and M2 will both benefit from mutual inbreeding avoidance. Both males will lose fitness if either inbreeds with F1, but each will lose more if he avoids inbreeding with F1 but his male relative inbreeds with F1. The decision for each male to inbreed with F1 or not can be modelled using a game-theoretic framework where payoffs are proportional to the inclusive fitness benefits for different mating situations. A full game-theoretic model is beyond the scope of this paper, but a simple example illustrates a basic framework.

For simplicity, we assume an outbred population and define r = rM1,F1 = rM2,F1 = rM1,M2 and δ = δM1,F1 = δM2,F1. To further simplify the notation, we assume F1 produces two offspring (n = 2), so n2=1 when calculating inclusive fitness; changing this assumption does not affect the relative payoffs of different mating situations and therefore does not affect the generality of the model. We further assume no opportunity cost of inbreeding (i.e., c = 0). If both M1 and M2 avoid inbreeding, we assume F1 outbreeds with a different unrelated male. Both M1 and M2 therefore have an indirect fitness benefit of r (nr2). If M1 inbreeds but M2 does not, then M1’s inclusive fitness is (1 + r)(1 − δ), while M2’s inclusive fitness is 2r(1 − δ), with the opposite inclusive fitness payoffs if M1 avoids inbreeding and M2 inbreeds. If both M1 and M2 attempt to inbreed, we assume no shared paternity and that each has an equal chance of success; therefore each receives an expected inclusive fitness payoff of 12[(1+r)(1δ)+2r(1δ)]=12(1+3r)(1δ).

These payoffs can be placed in a matrix (Table 1) to determine the evolutionary stable strategy (ESS [69]) of inbreeding for M1 and M2 in terms of r and δ. For many combinations of r and δ, the ESS for each male is pure (i.e., always inbreed or avoid inbreeding). For example, if M1, F1, and M2 are full siblings of outbred parents (r=12), and inbreeding depression is complete (δ = 1), then M1 benefits only if both he and M2 avoid inbreeding. Inbreeding avoidance is therefore an ESS for M1 (i.e., M1 should always avoid inbreeding), but the maximum payoff is only realised if M2 also avoids inbreeding. In contrast, if there is no inbreeding depression (δ = 0), attempting to inbreed always gives M1 a higher payoff, even if M2 also attempts to inbreed.

thumbnail
Table 1. A general payoff matrix for male relatives (M1, M2) for either inbreeding or avoiding inbreeding with a female (F1) of equally close relatedness (r).

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0125140.t001

Interestingly, a mixed strategy, in which inbreeding avoidance is probabilistic, is an ESS for a narrow range of intermediate values. For example, if δ=1320, then both M1 and M2 have an inclusive fitness benefit of 12 in the case of mutual inbreeding avoidance, but only 516 if both attempt to inbreed. If M1 inbreeds but M2 avoids inbreeding, then M1 will receive a payoff of 2140, greater than if both mutually inbreed or avoid inbreeding. In contrast, M2 receives a payoff of only 720. This payoff matrix has the format of a Hawk-Dove game [69, 70] in which the ESS for M1 (and M2) is mixed (i.e., for each interaction, a strategy is selected with some probability). Instead of an absolute inbreeding avoidance, preference, or tolerance strategy, a probabilistic strategy might therefore be predicted in some circumstances. This basic model makes multiple restrictive assumptions, but it suggests that a game-theoretic approach might be useful for understanding mating conflicts among male relatives.

Predictive models of inbreeding strategy

Our models imply that the inclusive fitness costs and benefits of inbreeding versus avoiding inbreeding will vary among individuals depending on their interactions with multiple different relatives of both sexes, and on the degree to which focal individuals are themselves inbred. Understanding these costs and benefits and their combined consequences for the evolution of inbreeding strategies therefore requires consideration of not only the relatedness of an individual to its potential mate(s), but also the relatedness between the individual and the subsequent mates of rejected relatives. Knowledge of the distribution of relatedness within a population is therefore likely to be critical for understanding the evolution of inbreeding strategies. This distribution will in turn depend on the distribution of relatedness in previous generations and on previously realised inbreeding strategies and inbreeding loads, thereby generating complex feedbacks between inbreeding strategy, load, and relatedness. Because of the complexity inherent in these systems, neither our conceptual model presented here nor its predecessors [2428] should be interpreted as providing quantitatively accurate predictions of inbreeding depression thresholds underlying inbreeding avoidance versus preference that might apply to empirical systems (as is sometimes attempted [3134]).

A comprehensive theory of biparental inbreeding strategy will require new models that explicitly consider interactions among numerous relatives [10]. Because sexual conflict over inbreeding is predicted [10, 24], the ultimate evolution of inbreeding strategy will depend on the degree to which conflict is resolved in favour of males versus females [25]. Inbreeding strategy might also depend on the encounter rate between potential mates. Like most predecessors [2426, 28], our model implicitly assumes that individuals have a rapid encounter rate among potential mates. Kokko and Ots [27] relaxed this assumption, and showed that greater inbreeding depression is required to make inbreeding avoidance beneficial given sequential rather than simultaneous mate encounters (see also [29]). A general, comprehensive theory of inbreeding must therefore propose some resolution of sexual conflict and consider appropriate aspects of life-history and population ecology.

Sexual conflict and interactions among multiple non-self relatives are particular to biparental reproduction rather than self-fertilisation, but both types of inbreeding increase the expression of inbreeding load causing inbreeding depression in offspring [1, 2, 7, 12]. Inbreeding depression may decrease inbreeding load by exposing deleterious homozygous recessive alleles to selection [9, 71]. Resulting purging of deleterious recessive alleles may in turn affect the inclusive fitness benefit of inbreeding versus avoiding inbreeding causing inbreeding strategy and inbreeding load to coevolve [12, 72, 73]. The consequences of this coevolution have been modelled extensively with respect to outcrossing versus selfing [12, 18, 72, 7476], but have not yet been modelled for the evolution of biparental inbreeding strategies [10]. Future theoretical developments will therefore need to explicitly consider coevolution between biparental inbreeding strategy and inbreeding load.

Predictive models of biparental inbreeding evolution cannot be simple, but their complexity need not preclude generality [77]. Tractable approaches for developing inbreeding theory might include game-theoretic models, or individual-based models that explicitly track ancestry and inbreeding load, and thereby incorporate feedbacks among relatedness, load, and inbreeding strategy.

Supporting Information

S1 File. Consequences of assuming that inbreeding depression in offspring is a linear function of parental kinship.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0125140.s001

(PDF)

Acknowledgments

We thank Greta Bocedi, Sylvain Losdat, Matthew Wolak, and several anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments.

Author Contributions

Analyzed the data: ABD JMR. Wrote the paper: ABD JMR. Evolutionary Modelling: ABD JMR.

References

  1. 1. Goodwillie C, Kalisz S, Eckert CG. The evolutionary enigma of mixed mating systems in plants: occurrence, theoretical explanations, and empirical evidence. Annu Rev Ecol Evol Syst. 2005;36: 47–79.
  2. 2. Charlesworth D. Evolution of plant breeding systems. Curr Biol. 2006;16: R726–R735. pmid:16950099
  3. 3. Charlesworth D, Willis JH. The genetics of inbreeding depression. Nat Rev Genet. 2009;10: 783–796. pmid:19834483
  4. 4. Pusey AE. Sex-biased dispersal and inbreeding avoidance in birds and mammals. Trends Ecol Evol. 1987;2:295–299. pmid:21227869
  5. 5. Szulkin M, Sheldon BC. Dispersal as a means of inbreeding avoidance in a wild bird population. Proc R Soc Lond B. 2008;275: 703–711.
  6. 6. Saccheri I, Kuussaari M, Kankare M, Vikman P, Hanski IA. Inbreeding and extinction in a butterfly metapopulation. Nature. 1998;45: 1996–1999.
  7. 7. Keller LF, Waller DM. Inbreeding effects in wild populations. Trends Ecol Evol. 2002;17: 19–23.
  8. 8. Byers DL, Waller DM. Do plant populations purge their genetic load? Effects of population size and mating history on inbreeding depression. Annu Rev Ecol Syst. 1999;30: 479–513.
  9. 9. Crnokrak P, Barrett SCH. Perspective: purging the genetic load: a review of the experimental evidence. Evolution. 2002;56: 2347–2358. pmid:12583575
  10. 10. Szulkin M, Stopher KV, Pemberton JM, Reid JM. Inbreeding avoidance, tolerance, or preference in animals? Trends Ecol Evol. 2013;28: 205–211. pmid:23182684
  11. 11. Charlesworth B. The cost of sex in relation to mating system. J Theor Biol. 1980;84: 655–671. pmid:7431946
  12. 12. Lande R, Schemske DW. The evolution of self-fertilization and inbreeding depression in plants. I. Genetic models. Evolution. 1985;39: 24–40.
  13. 13. Lloyd D. Self- and cross-fertilization in plants. II. The selection of self-fertilization. Int J Plant Sci. 1992;153: 370–380.
  14. 14. Tsitrone A, Duperron S, David P. Delayed selfing as an optimal mating strategy in preferentially outcrossing species: theoretical analysis of the optimal age at first reproduction in relation to mate availability. Am Nat. 2003;162: 318–331. pmid:12970840
  15. 15. Porcher E, Lande R. The evolution of self-fertilization and inbreeding depression under pollen discounting and pollen limitation. J Evol Biol. 2005;18: 497–508. pmid:15842479
  16. 16. Porcher E, Kelly JK, Cheptou PO, Eckert CG, Johnston MO, Kalisz S. The genetic consequences of fluctuating inbreeding depression and the evolution of plant selfing rates. J Evol Biol. 2009;22: 708–717. pmid:19228271
  17. 17. Fisher RA. Average excess and average effect of a gene substitution. Ann Eugen. 1941;11: 53–63.
  18. 18. Schultz ST, Willis JH. Individual variation in inbreeding depression: the roles of inbreeding history and mutation. Genetics. 1995;141: 1209–1223. pmid:8582625
  19. 19. Crnokrak P, Roff DA. Inbreeding depression in the wild. Heredity. 1999;83: 260–270. pmid:10504423
  20. 20. Armbruster P, Reed DH. Inbreeding depression in benign and stressful environments. Heredity. 2005;95: 235–242. pmid:16077737
  21. 21. Blouin SF, Blouin M. Inbreeding avoidance behaviors. Trends Ecol Evol. 1988;3: 230–233. pmid:21227237
  22. 22. Pusey A, Wolf M. Inbreeding avoidance in animals. Trends Ecol Evol. 1996;5347: 298–301.
  23. 23. Tennenhouse EM. Inbreeding avoidance in male primates: a response to female mate choice? Ethology. 2014;120: 111–119.
  24. 24. Parker GA. Sexual selection and sexual conflict. In: Blum MS, Blum NA, editors. Sexual selection and reproductive competition in insects. New York: Academic Press, Inc; 1979. p. 123–166.
  25. 25. Parker GA. Sexual conflict over mating and fertilization: an overview. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2006;361:235–259. pmid:16612884
  26. 26. Waser PM, Austad SN, Keane B. When should animals tolerate inbreeding? Am Nat. 1986;128: 529–537.
  27. 27. Kokko H, Ots I. When not to avoid inbreeding. Evolution. 2006;60: 467–475. pmid:16637492
  28. 28. Puurtinen M. Mate choice for optimal (k)inbreeding. Evolution. 2011;65: 1501–1505. pmid:21521199
  29. 29. Jamieson IG, Taylor SS, Tracy LN, Kokko H, Armstrong DP. Why some species of birds do not avoid inbreeding: insights from New Zealand robins and saddlebacks. Behav Ecol. 2009;20: 575–584.
  30. 30. Clutton-Brock T, Parker GA. Sexual coercion in animal societies. Anim Behav. 1995;49: 1345–1365.
  31. 31. Ala-Honkola O, Uddström A, Pauli BD, Lindström K. Strong inbreeding depression in male mating behaviour in a poeciliid fish. J Evol Biol. 2009;22: 1396–1406. pmid:19486236
  32. 32. Kuriwada T, Kumano N, Shiromoto K, Haraguchi D. Inbreeding avoidance or tolerance? Comparison of mating behavior between mass-reared and wild strains of the sweet potato weevil. Behav Ecol Sociobiol. 2011;65: 1483–1489.
  33. 33. Kuriwada T, Kumano N, Shiromoto K, Haraguchi D. The effect of inbreeding on mating behaviour of West Indian sweet potato weevil Euscepes postfasciatus. Ethology. 2011;117:822–828.
  34. 34. Tan CKW, LØvlie H, Pizzari T, Wigby S. No evidence for precopulatory inbreeding avoidance in Drosophila melanogaster. Anim Behav. 2012;83: 1433–1441.
  35. 35. Wright S. Coefficients of inbreeding and relationship. Am Nat. 1922;56: 330–338.
  36. 36. Lehmann L, Perrin N. Inbreeding avoidance through kin recognition: choosy females boost male dispersal. Am Nat. 2003;162: 638–652. pmid:14618541
  37. 37. Hamilton WD. Altruism and related phenomena, mainly in social insects. Annu Rev Ecol Syst. 1972;3: 193–232.
  38. 38. Michod RE, Anderson WW. Measures of genetic relationship and the concept of inclusive fitness. Am Nat. 1979;114: 637–647.
  39. 39. Morton NE, Crow JF, Muller HJ. An estimate of the mutational damage in man from data on consanguineous marriages. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A. 1956;42: 855–863. pmid:16589958
  40. 40. Mills LS, Smouse PE. Demographic consequences of inbreeding in remnant populations. Am Nat. 1994;144: 412–431.
  41. 41. Ralls K, Ballou JD, Templeton A. Estimates of lethal equivalents and the cost of inbreeding in mammals. Conserv Biol. 1988;2: 185–193.
  42. 42. Keane B, Creel SR, Waser PM. No evidence of inbreeding avoidance or inbreeding depression in a social carnivore. Behav Ecol. 1996;7: 480–489.
  43. 43. Jennions MD, Hunt J, Graham R, Brooks R. No evidence for inbreeding avoidance through postcopulatory mechanisms in the black field cricket, Teleogryllus commodus. Evolution. 2004;58: 2472–2477. pmid:15612290
  44. 44. Hoarau G, Boon E, Jongma DN, Ferber S, Palsson J, Van der Veer HW, et al. Low effective population size and evidence for inbreeding in an overexploited flatfish, plaice (Pleuronectes platessa L.). Proc R Soc Lond B. 2005;272: 497–503.
  45. 45. Schmoll T, Quellmalz A, Dietrich V, Winkel W, Epplen JT, Lubjuhn T. Genetic similarity between pair mates is not related to extrapair paternity in the socially monogamous coal tit. Anim Behav. 2005;69: 1013–1022.
  46. 46. Holand O, Askim KR, Roed KH, Weladji RB, Gjostein H, Nieminen M. No evidence of inbreeding avoidance in a polygynous ungulate: the reindeer (Rangifer tarandus). Biol Lett. 2007;3: 36–39. pmid:17443960
  47. 47. Billing AM, Lee AM, Skjelseth S, Borg AA, Hale MC, Slate J, et al. Evidence of inbreeding depression but not inbreeding avoidance in a natural house sparrow population. Mol Ecol. 2012;21: 1487–1499. pmid:22335620
  48. 48. Cohen LB, Dearborn DC. Great frigatebirds, Fregata minor, choose mates that are genetically similar. Anim Behav. 2004;68: 1229–1236.
  49. 49. Kleven O, Jacobsen F, Robertson RJ, Lifjeld JT. Extrapair mating between relatives in the barn swallow: a role for kin selection? Biol Lett. 2005;1: 389–392. pmid:17148214
  50. 50. Wang C, Lu X. Female ground tits prefer relatives as extra-pair partners: driven by kin-selection? Mol Ecol. 2011;20: 2851–2863. pmid:21438933
  51. 51. Olson LE, Blumstein DT, Pollinger JR, Wayne RK. No evidence of inbreeding avoidance despite demonstrated survival costs in a polygynous rodent. Mol Ecol. 2012;21: 562–571. pmid:22145620
  52. 52. Robinson SP, Kennington WJ, Simmons LW. Preference for related mates in the fruit fly, Drosophila melanogaster. Anim Behav. 2012;84: 1169–1176.
  53. 53. Chapman T, Arnqvist G, Bangham J, Rowe L. Sexual conflict. Trends Ecol Evol. 2003;18: 41–47.
  54. 54. Grafen A. Optimization of inclusive fitness. J Theor Biol. 2006;238: 541–563. pmid:16046225
  55. 55. Ohtsuki H. Evolutionary dynamics of n-player games played by relatives. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2014;369: 20130359. pmid:24686931
  56. 56. Grafen A. The hawk-dove game played between relatives. Anim Behav. 1979;27: 905–907.
  57. 57. Uyenoyama MK. Inbreeding and the cost of meiosis: the evolution of selfing in populations practicing biparental inbreeding. Evolution. 1986;40: 388–404.
  58. 58. Nason JD, Ellstrand NC. Lifetime estimates of biparental inbreeding depression in the self-incompatible annual plant Raphanus sativus. Evolution. 1995;49: 307–316.
  59. 59. Herlihy CR, Eckert CG. Experimental dissection of inbreeding and its adaptive significance in a flowering plant, Aquilegia canadensis (Ranunculaceae). Evolution. 2004;58: 2693–2703. pmid:15696748
  60. 60. Hirao AS. Kinship between parents reduces offspring fitness in a natural population of Rhododendron brachycarpum. Ann Bot. 2010;105: 637–646. pmid:20202970
  61. 61. Arnqvist G, Rowe L. Sexual Conflict. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press; 2005.
  62. 62. Emlen ST. An evolutionary theory of the family. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A. 1995;92: 8092–8099. pmid:7667250
  63. 63. Sharp SP, Simeoni M, Hatchwell BJ. Dispersal of sibling coalitions promotes helping among immigrants in a cooperatively breeding bird. Proc R Soc Lond B. 2008;275: 2125–2130.
  64. 64. Hinde CA, Johnstone RA, Kilner RM. Parent-offspring conflict and coadaptation. Science. 2010;327: 1373–1376. pmid:20223985
  65. 65. Stucki D, Mathias K. Coevolutionary feedbacks between family interactions and life history. Evolution. 2013;67: 3208–3220. pmid:24152003
  66. 66. Haig D. Asymmetric relations: Internal conflicts and the horror of incest. Evol Hum Behav. 1999;98: 83–98.
  67. 67. Welbergen JA, Quader S. Mother guarding: how offspring may influence the extra-pair behaviour of their parents. Proc R Soc Lond B. 2006;273: 2363–2368.
  68. 68. Parker GA, Partridge L. Sexual conflict and speciation. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 1998;353: 261–274. pmid:9533125
  69. 69. Maynard Smith J, Price GR. The logic of animal conflict. Nature. 1973;246: 15–18.
  70. 70. Maynard Smith J, Parker GA. The logic of asymmetric contests. Anim Behav. 1976;24: 159–175.
  71. 71. Barrett SCH, Charlesworth D. Effects of a change in the level of inbreeding on genetic load. Nature. 1991;352:522–524. pmid:1865906
  72. 72. Uyenoyama MK, Waller DM. Coevolution of self-fertilization and inbreeding depression. I. Mutation-selection balance at one and two loci. Theor Popul Biol. 1991;40: 14–46. pmid:1948770
  73. 73. Escobar JS, Auld JR, Correa AC, Alonso JM, Bony YK, Coutellec MA, et al. Patterns of mating-system evolution in hermaphroditic animals: correlations among selfing rate, inbreeding depression, and the timing of reproduction. Evolution. 2011;65: 1233–1253. pmid:21521187
  74. 74. Uyenoyama MK, Waller DM. Coevolution of self-fertilization and inbreeding depression. III. Homozygous lethal mutations at multiple loci. Theor Ecol. 1991;40: 173–210.
  75. 75. Glémin S. How are deleterious mutations purged? Drift versus nonrandom mating. Evolution. 2003;57: 2678–2687. pmid:14761049
  76. 76. Roze D, Blanckaert A. Epistasis, pleiotropy, and the mutation load in sexual and asexual populations. Evolution. 2014;68: 137–49. pmid:24372600
  77. 77. Evans MR, Grimm V, Johst K, Knuuttila T, de Langhe R, Lessells CM, et al. Do simple models lead to generality in ecology? Trends Ecol Evol. 2013;28: 578–583. pmid:23827437